Down the foxhole

By Sancho McCann ·

In our Property Law course, we are now read­ing about pos­ses­sion. Our case book men­tioned Pierson v Post in a note, and that led me down a trail of read­ing this past week.

The facts

Lodowick Post was in pur­suit of a fox. Another per­son, Jesse Pierson, killed the fox and took it for him­self. The is­sue is whether Post has any prop­er­ty right in the fox that he was hunt­ing.

The decision

The court held that “mere pur­suit gave Post no le­gal right to the fox, but that he be­came the prop­er­ty of Pierson, who in­ter­cept­ed and killed him.” They seem to give two justifications for this ap­proach. The first is a first-oc­cu­pan­cy or first-pos­ses­sion justification:

the mor­tal wound­ing of such beasts, by one not aban­don­ing his pur­suit, may, with the ut­most pro­pri­ety, be deemed pos­ses­sion of him; since, there­by, the pur­suer man­i­fests an un­equiv­o­cal in­ten­tion of ap­pro­pri­at­ing the an­i­mal to his in­di­vid­ual use, has de­prived him of his nat­ur­al lib­er­ty, and brought him with­in his cer­tain con­trol (em­pha­sis mine)

They also give a justification from en­force­ment efficiency: “for the sake of cer­tain­ty, and pre­serv­ing peace and or­der in so­ci­ety.” They pre­dict that if they were to rule that mere pur­suit gives rise to a prop­er­ty right, “it would prove a fer­tile source of quar­rels and lit­i­ga­tion.”

The dis­sent (Judge Henry Livingstone) dis­agrees and gives an ar­gu­ment based on ju­di­cial def­er­ence, labour, eco­nom­ic efficiency, and some in­ter­est­ing as­sump­tions about the role of the fox hunt in New York in 1805.

First, Livingstone says the court should have just asked the “sports­men” (the fox hunters) what would rule would have made sense in the con­text of their ac­tiv­i­ty. (Today, this con­tex­tu­al ap­proach has been em­braced in the com­mon law.

Regarding labour, eco­nom­ic in­cen­tives, and the role of the fox hunt, he says (em­pha­sis and trans­la­tions mine):

By the plead­ings it is ad­mit­ted that a fox is a “wild and nox­ious beast.” Both par­ties have re­gard­ed him, as the law of na­tions does a pi­rate, “hostem hu­mani gen­er­is,” [en­e­my of mankind] and al­though “de mor­tu­is nil nisi bon­um,” [of the dead, say noth­ing but good] be a max­im of our pro­fes­sion, the mem­o­ry of the de­ceased has not been spared. His de­pre­da­tions on farm­ers and on barn yards, have not been for­got­ten; and to put him to death wher­ev­er found, is al­lowed to be mer­i­to­ri­ous, and of pub­lic benefit. Hence it fol­lows, that our de­ci­sion should have in view the great­est pos­si­ble en­cour­age­ment to the de­struc­tion of an an­i­mal, so cun­ning and ruth­less in his ca­reer. But who would keep a pack of hounds; or what gen­tle­man, at the sound of the horn, and at peep of day, would mount his steed, and for hours to­geth­er, “sub jove fri­gi­do,” [un­der cold Jupiter] or a ver­ti­cal sun, pur­sue the wind­ings of this wily quadruped, if, just as night came on, and his strat­a­gems and strength were near­ly ex­haust­ed, a saucy in­trud­er, who had not shared in the ho­n­ours or labours of the chase, were per­mit­ted to come in at the death, and bear away in tri­umph the ob­ject of pur­suit?

Economic efficiency

Livingstone is ar­gu­ing that there is so­cial good in killing fox­es, par­tic­u­lar­ly be­cause of their dam­age to farm an­i­mals. It’s im­por­tant to en­cour­age the fox hunt be­cause it kills fox­es. If a hunter who spent a bunch of effort on pur­su­ing a fox might lose it to a “saucy in­trud­er”, there will be few­er hunters will­ing to put in that effort, and there will be few­er fox­es killed. So, let’s not re­ward that in­trud­er with own­er­ship of the fox.

These are not ob­vi­ous moves. You might think—a lot of peo­ple think—that judges mere­ly try to dis­cov­er what the law is. And some peo­ple think that is a search for some­thing called “nat­ur­al law”: law that ex­ists in­de­pen­dent­ly of our par­tic­u­lar cir­cum­stances and so­ci­eties—ob­jec­tive moral truth. Or, slight­ly less ex­treme, that judges are search­ing for a rule that is based on long-stand­ing, even though so­cial­ly con­tin­gent, ideas about what is right in a moral sense. This case makes it clear that judges some­times make law, and they some­times make law based on prag­mat­ic con­cerns and eco­nom­ic con­cerns. I don’t know how of­ten it was that judges con­sid­ered these in­ter­ests in 1805 or how ex­plic­it­ly they typ­i­cal­ly pre­sent­ed those justifications in their de­ci­sions.

Economic-efficiency ar­gu­ments are tricky. You have to (at least im­plic­it­ly) choose a “wel­fare” func­tion: an ac­count­ing of things that you aim to have more or less of. A pa­per by Dharmapala and Pitchford ac­tu­al­ly works through the effect that the ma­jor­i­ty’s rule and Livingstone’s rule would have on the num­ber of fox­es killed. The re­sults un­der their ini­tial as­sump­tions rough­ly match Livingstone’s in­tu­ition in his dis­sent. The pa­per is fair­ly read­able even if you ig­nore every equa­tion.

Thinking about prop­er­ty al­lo­ca­tion from this eco­nom­ic per­spec­tive is only a tool for ex­press­ing rea­sons; it doesn’t pro­vide rea­sons on its own. What you choose to cap­ture in the wel­fare func­tion can near­ly an­swer the ques­tion for you. In Dharmapala and Pitchford’s ar­ti­cle, they in­clud­ed the price per pelt, en­joy­ment of the hunt, dam­age avert­ed to farm an­i­mals, in­vest­ment by the hunter, and in­vest­ment by the saucy in­trud­er. What about oth­er ex­ter­nal­i­ties? Enforcement/lit­i­ga­tion costs might be significantly different un­der each of the rules. In fact, the ma­jor­i­ty ar­gues this, and Dharmapala and Pitchford ex­pand their wel­fare func­tion to in­clude en­force­ment costs lat­er in the pa­per. This just high­lights how the definition of the so­cial wel­fare func­tion is a po­lit­i­cal ques­tion. And, the max­i­miza­tion of it is con­tin­gent on ac­tu­al facts, some of which might not ac­tu­al­ly be known or know­able. Why does the orig­i­nal hunter get zero pos­i­tive en­joy­ment when the in­trud­er gets the fox? Even as­sum­ing that the pos­i­tive ex­pe­ri­ence dur­ing the hunt is di­min­ished when the in­trud­er gets the fox, why does it can­cel per­fect­ly to zero?

It turns out that hunters found plea­sure in the hunt even if they didn’t end up catch­ing a fox. They also may have sought to main­tain the fox pop­u­la­tion. A “bagged” (live) fox was worth more than a dead fox. Again, this demon­strates that eco­nom­ic ar­gu­ments are only as con­vinc­ing as the fac­tors they con­sid­er.

How would the Coase the­o­rem ap­ply here? Perhaps the hunters would pay peo­ple to stay clear of their hunt. The hunters would have to pay the in­trud­ers as much mon­ey as they’d oth­er­wise be able to fetch by free­load­ing. But this seems un­ten­able, be­cause more and more peo­ple could show up de­mand­ing pay­ment to stay out of the way of the hunt. Historically, though, it seems that rather than the in­trud­ers be­ing mere free­load­ers, they were farm­ers just try­ing to en­sure the fox­es got killed, to pre­vent in­jury to their own an­i­mals. If the only peo­ple that were in­trud­ing were farm­ers at risk of los­ing an­i­mals to fox­es, then a Coasian so­lu­tion could ac­tu­al­ly play out. The hunters would pay the farm­ers for dam­age that hap­pens to come to their farms due to fox­es: a kind of tax/in­sur­ance for hav­ing a pure hunt. Another op­tion would be pay­ments to the own­er(s) of the land on which the hunt takes place in ex­change for the ex­clu­sive right to hunt. (Although, the fox in Pierson v Post was killed on a pub­lic beach.)

Application: cybersquatting

Where does this kind of sit­u­a­tion oc­cur to­day? The sit­u­a­tion, ab­stract­ly, is that there are two groups of peo­ple seek­ing benefit from a lim­it­ed re­source. The re­source is such that it takes some effort to ex­tract val­ue from that re­source and the per­son to ini­ti­ate that effort doesn’t nec­es­sar­i­ly gain ex­clu­sive pos­ses­sion of that val­ue for quite some time, leav­ing room for a “saucy in­trud­er” to cut in and free­load or hold hostage the val­ue de­sired by the per­son who un­der­took the ini­tial in­vest­ment of effort.

Dharmapala and Pitchford ar­gue that cy­ber­squat­ting match­es this sce­nario. Should a do­main name be giv­en to the first per­son to reg­is­ter it with­out re­gard to whether an­oth­er has al­ready de­vel­oped a brand around that name? Or should a per­son who has put in the “ho­n­our and labour” of de­vel­op­ing a com­pa­ny and brand have rights to the as­so­ci­at­ed do­main name? It turns out that in cas­es of pure cy­ber­squat­ting (as op­posed to du­al­ing brands), the com­mon law, and now leg­is­la­tion, has ap­plied a rule anal­o­gous to Livingstone’s rule: the com­pa­ny with the de­vel­oped brand gets the do­main, rather than the cy­ber­squat­ter.

Application: patent law

This analy­sis has also been ap­plied to crit­i­cize some out­comes of patent law.

Patent law can re­sult in a di­vi­sion of rights be­tween an ini­tial in­ven­tor and sub­se­quent in­ven­tors that im­prove upon the orig­i­nal. An in­ven­tor can only pro­tect, ex­clude, and ex­ploit that which they’ve ac­tu­al­ly in­vent­ed. Improvements are patentable sep­a­rate­ly by sub­se­quent in­ven­tors. But a sub­se­quent in­ven­tor hav­ing im­proved upon a pre­vi­ous patent could not sell the im­proved vari­ant with­out a li­cence from the hold­er of the orig­i­nal patent when that im­prove­ment builds upon the orig­i­nal., And, the orig­i­nal in­ven­tor would need to get a li­cence from the im­prover in or­der to use their im­prove­ment.

The cur­rent law re­wards ear­ly in­vest­ment. We give patents to in­ven­tions that might not be mar­ket-ready. Patent law does not re­quire com­mer­cial vi­a­bil­i­ty. However, patent law also re­wards sub­se­quent in­vest­ment by oth­er in­ven­tors. It might take less in­vest­ment to take the in­ven­tion from its ear­li­est-patentable state to a com­mer­cial­ly-vi­able state. Improvers can ride on the ear­ly suc­cess of the orig­i­nal patent-hold­er, but they can’t free-ride. The im­prover can’t ac­tu­al­ly sell the com­mer­cial­ly-vi­able prod­uct if it still uses the orig­i­nal in­ven­tion. However, the im­prover could ex­clude the orig­i­nal in­ven­tor from us­ing the par­tic­u­lar im­prove­ment that is patent­ed by the im­prover. This could be used to ex­tract a li­cens­ing fee from the orig­i­nal in­ven­tor in or­der to make, use, or sell the im­prover’s com­mer­cial­ly-vi­able vari­ant. Here, we see a mixed-al­lo­ca­tion of rights in ac­tion.

But, what if we al­lo­cate rights too ear­ly? What if the orig­i­nal in­ven­tor gets rights while they are still in “mere pur­suit” of the in­ven­tion? As per Livingstone’s analy­sis, this will dis­cour­age the saucy in­trud­er. Here, though, the saucy in­trud­er is a would-be in­ven­tor, a would-be im­prover. We don’t want to dis­cour­age this ac­tiv­i­ty. That would work against the goals of the patent sys­tem.

Oullette ar­gues that this hap­pens when we give peo­ple patents that are too spec­u­la­tive and that re­quire un­due ex­per­i­men­ta­tion on the part of any­one want­i­ng to use the patent. These patents don’t do much to low­er the bar­ri­er to fur­ther im­prove­ment, but they re­ward the orig­i­nal “in­ven­tor” with an un­earned right to ex­clude. This dis­cour­ages the flurry of im­prove­ment patents that one might nor­mal­ly see af­ter a sufficiently dis­closed in­ven­tion is patent­ed. She ar­gues that this is a de­fect in the ex­am­i­na­tion process.

How people use this case

I found an ar­ti­cle by Luke Meier on us­ing Pierson v Post as the first case in prop­er­ty law. This is al­most a tran­script of how he would teach his first few class­es.

It seems that it’s com­mon to use this as the first case in a prop­er­ty law course. We didn’t look at this case first. We start­ed by think­ing about what rights are part of the bun­dle of rights called prop­er­ty, how those are con­tex­tu­al, and the different roles that prop­er­ty rights fill in our so­ci­ety. Only now, sev­en weeks in, are we start­ing to look at what is re­quired, or what should be re­quired, to gain pos­ses­sion of a thing.